Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick, "Teaching/Depression"
(page 2 of 6)
To move from Silvan Tomkins's account of the depressive [person] to
Melanie Klein's account of the depressive position is like moving from a
minoritizing to a universalizing discourse. If Tomkins's depressive is a
particular kind of individual who emerges from the contingency of
a particular history with the strengths and weaknesses of a particular
interpretive and performative strategy, Klein's depressive position, to
the contrary, is a developmental phase - a developmental achievement - that
is potentially available to everyone. Moreover, the depressive position
is a uniquely spacious rubric. Despite its name it encompasses, for
example, both the preconditions of severe depression and also the
resources for surviving, repairing, and moving far beyond that
depression.
For Klein, the depressive position is one of only two positions - two
modes of relationality - available to human creatures. And while the
depressive position marks a developmental achievement over its
alternative, the fragile paranoid/schizoid position, it is not a
permanent achievement but part of a fluid, back-and-forth process
between the two positions. What defines the paranoid/schizoid position,
in all its fragility, are three rather violent things: the ego's
inability to tolerate anxiety or ambivalence; its consequent strategy of
splitting both its objects and itself into fragments that can be seen as
exclusively good or bad; and its aggressive expulsion of intolerable
parts of itself onto - or in Klein's more graphic locution,
into - the person who is taken as an object. Klein writes that
these "bad parts of the self are meant not only to injure but also to
control and to take possession of the object" (Klein, 8); she calls this
mechanism "projective identification." Projective identification is
related to Freudian projection but is more uncannily intrusive: for
Freud, when I've projected my hostility onto you, I believe that you
dislike me; for Klein, when I've projected my hostility into you,
you do dislike me. Projective identification is thus a good way
of understanding, for example, the terrifying contagion of paranoid
modes of thought - and as we'll see, it certainly seems indispensable for
a lot of political analysis and group dynamics. But it's also a helpful
way of understanding things that can go so painfully wrong in the
classroom. For instance, a professor who's unable to tolerate or contain
the anxieties of competition may run a classroom in which all find
themselves unusually anxious about power or disempowerment. A
professor's disavowed issues about originality can turn into a maelstrom
of plagiarism anxieties that circulate in all directions. Or a professor
who is unable to provide a home to her own discomforts about sexuality
can accumulate a group of students whose learning process is clogged
with manipulative or resentful scenes of seduction. All this is not even
to mention the projective identifications that originate with our
students, who can be just as self-ignorant or as disruptively
charismatic as ourselves, if not more so. Again both in and beyond the
classroom many of us, I think, are familiar with situations where our
own or other people's preemptive need to disown feelings of racism,
misogyny, anti-Semitism, and so forth - feelings that almost inevitably
arise but are experienced as intolerable - is liable to propel circuits of
interpersonal accusation that are explosive with the very forms of
hatred that are under internal erasure.
Thus for Klein's infant or adult, the paranoid/schizoid
position - marked by hatred, envy, and anxiety - is a position of terrible
alertness to the dangers posed by the hateful and envious part-objects
that one defensively projects into the world around one. The depressive
position, by contrast, is an anxiety-mitigating achievement which the
infant or adult only sometimes, and often only briefly, succeeds in
inhabiting. What makes the depressive position "depressive"? The
threshold to the depressive position is the foundational, authentically
difficult understanding that good and bad tend to be inseparable at
every level. "The infant," as one Kleinian summarizes this argument, "at
some stage . . . is physically and emotionally mature enough to
integrate his or her fragmented perceptions, bringing together the
separately good and bad versions. . . . When such part-objects are
brought together as a whole they threaten to form a contaminated,
damaged, or dead whole object," whether internal, external, or
both - what I take to be a description of the experience of depression per
se (Hinshelwood 138, emphasis added).
"Depressive anxiety," this account continues, "is the crucial element
of mature relationships, the source of generous and altruistic feelings
that are devoted to the well-being of the object" (138). This, then, is
the position from which it is possible to begin using one's own
resources to assemble or "repair" the part-objects into something like a
whole, albeit a compromised one. Once assembled, these more realistic,
durable, and in that sense satisfying objects are available to be
identified with, to offer one and to be offered nourishment and comfort
in turn. Yet the pressures of that founding, depressive realization can
also continually impel the ego back toward depression, toward manic
escapism, or toward the violently projective defenses of the
paranoid/schizoid position. We feel these depressive pressures in the
forms of remorse, shame, confusion, depression itself, mourning for the
lost ideal, and - often most relevant - a sad understanding of the
inexorable laws of unintended consequences.
My own sense is that activist politics, even more than pedagogy,
takes place - even at best - just at this difficult nexus between the
paranoid/schizoid and the depressive positions. Suppose the
paranoid/schizoid, entirely caught up in splitting and projection, to be
always saying, like Harold Bloom or even George W. Bush, "Those others
are all about ressentiment." Suppose the depressive to be able to
say at least intermittently, "We, like those others, are subject to the
imperious dynamics of ressentiment; now how can the dynamics
themselves become different?" It would certainly be presumptuous for me
to suppose that the women represented here today all understand or do
activism in the same way, or at anything like the same depth, and I feel
out of my own depth in generalizing in this way. But as I understand my
own political history, it has often happened that the propulsive energy
of justification, of being or feeling joined with others in a right
cause, tends to be structured very much in a paranoid/schizoid fashion,
driven by attributed motives, fearful contempt of opponents, collective
fantasies of powerlessness and/or omnipotence, scapegoating, purism and
schism - paranoid/schizoid, in short, even as the motives that underlie
political commitment have much more to do with the complex, mature
ethical dimension of the depressive position.
What to make of the turn to life narrative in the context of such
split-natured and difficult activism and pedagogy? During the recent
political season I've been struck by one unabashedly paranoid/schizoid
kind of use of life narrative - as we've heard a phalanx of senators say
that while they may loathe the actions or principles of Alberto
Gonzales, for instance, it would be impossible to vote against his
story. And we've heard similar language about Condoleezza Rice's
"story" and Clarence Thomas's "story" and even John Edwards's "story,"
even if the latter of these did turn out to be possible to vote against.
A life story in this sense, Gonzalez's story, is less a narrative
than a compact consumer fetish, wholly instrumental, at once
inspirational and subtly accusatory, its own history effaced, perfectly
streamlined as a projectile to stop the mouths of his substantive
critics, and lodged in public consciousness as the insidiously potent
minimal unit of projective identification.
|