Rebecca Jordan-Young,
"Introduction"
(page 5 of 6)
Are the new reproductive technologies, in particular, which
aim towards "improving" reproduction with a range of high-tech
interventions, unavoidably eugenicist? The answer is complex. On the
one hand, many of the technologies (gamete donation, especially) are
advertised and used within a blunt discourse of "custom-building" ideal
babies, selecting the "fittest" eggs and sperm from young, healthy,
attractive and talented people, and trading on the long-standing science
fiction/fantasy that the complex traits and accomplishments of the
donors will be passed to offspring through the donor's DNA. Two of the
artistic entries in this issue—Critical Art Ensemble's (CAE) Flesh
Machine and the exhibit of pieces by the subRosa
Collective—capture the enticements of glamour, human perfectibility, and the
promise of a clean, bright future that propels the idealization of
science in this discourse. The racialization of "high quality" humans
is unavoidably white in this future, a point made in a no-nonsense way
by subRosa's "Calculate Your Fleshworth" worksheet, which assigns
specific values to your eggs or sperm based on your race. The eerily
white fantasy future projected by the imaginary "bioCom"/Flesh Machine
(CAE) corresponds all too well to the visual promise of white babies
made by the websites of real-world companies advertising surrogacy
services (even where the surrogates themselves are brown, as Waldby
describes).
And it's not just the sellers of services and materials in the
reproductive market that imagine a future of whiteness. In a
beautifully empathic and complex ethnography of clients of an IVF clinic
in Dubai, Marcia Inhorn relates the tale of "Eyad," a Palestinian man
who longs for (and apparently manages to obtain) the eggs of a white
donor he glimpses in the clinic. "In the future," Eyad tells Inhorn,
"all people will look like they are
Americans!"[20] Eyad's longing for
eggs from the "American-looking" donor is connected to his status as a
foreigner and history as a refugee, and it plainly articulates the
connection of race, national belonging, and transnational mobility:
'I hope my wife gets some eggs from that girl, because my
child, she'll be coming white—already American!—and not black like
my wife.' He added, facetiously, 'My child, when he comes, he will take
the American passport in the future.'
Should we call Eyad's longing eugenicist? Again, the answer is
complex. Historically, eugenics stemmed from a position of anxious
privilege: economically well-off white people concerned about a
perceived loss of control and a potential loss of authority and status.
Hierarchies embedded in discourse about reproduction of "the fit" did
and still do coincide with people's own hopes and plans for offspring
that would make them proud—but the alignment is sometimes a queer one.
The queerness comes from the difference between the message of dominant
discourse, and the conditions of its reception, most specifically
including one's relative position of privilege. 19th century
middle-class whites were concerned about degeneration: evolutionary
"backsliding" and "race suicide" seemed to threaten the privileges they
enjoyed and wished to secure for their heirs—among whom they counted
the "future nation" and "the (white) race." In the present, "successful
reproduction" for the privileged may similarly aim to prevent downward
economic and social mobility in an environment that is perceived as more
highly competitive and pressured than ever. I think it is right to name
as eugenic this "defensive" reproduction of the privileged—even when
it is practiced on a small scale rather than as a matter of social
policy, and even absent a conscious disavowal of "unfit" race, class,
sexual, or bodily types. But for people who are economically, socially,
and/or politically marginal, strategies for "successful reproduction"
may draw on the same hegemonic values (regarding race, ability, gender,
sexuality, and so on), but they can't ever be properly "eugenic" because
their aspirations for upward mobility involve a breach of the
fundamental purpose of eugenics: the reproduction of existing
hierarchies.
Sorting individual technologies or their users into
"eugenic/eugenicist" or not is, however, not the point. Instead, it is
useful to be alert to the potential these technologies have for
(re)animating some of the most pernicious modes of ranking human types
and traits. Questions we might return to again and again include: Whose
reproductive futures are highly valued, and whose are discounted in the
global reproductive market? How are specific technologically-assisted
reproductions built on those hierarchies, and how do they revitalize the
habit of ranking people and traits, as well as the specific content and
order of the hierarchies? How and when do reproductive technologies
disrupt the eugenic goal of reproducing hierarchies? For
example, a wide range of reproductive technologies are used to
facilitate reproduction among LGBT people, who are both historically and
currently "disfavored" reproducers by the dominant schema. Sperm
washing, chemotherapy during birth, and cesarean sections enable
reproduction among HIV+ women and men, though the dominant expectation
is that HIV+ people "should not" reproduce. As Gwendolyn Beetham's
exploration of first-person accounts from queers and infertile
heterosexuals suggests, reproductive technologies can and do "queer"
reproduction, even as they simultaneously reinforce certain normative
assumptions, such as the privileging of biological over adoptive
parenthood.
Page:
1 |
2 |
3 |
4 |
5 |
6
Next page
|